Divides
an integer n is divisible by another integer m if there exists an integer k such that n = k m . If this is all true we write m | n .
Divisible iff Integer Quotient
Suppose that a b iff b a Z
Suppose that a b , then there is some k Z such that a k = b therefore k = b a , and since k Z then b a Z as needed.
n Factorial is Divisible by Its Factors
For any k [ 1 , , n ] k n !
n ! = 1 k n therefore n ! k = 1 ( k k ) n Z so therefore k n !
Not Divisible iff Non-Integer Quotient
a b iff b a Z
By the fact that P Q iff ¬ P ¬ Q
1 Divides Everything
Suppose that j Z , then 1 | j
In the definition of divides take k = j , then we can see that j = j 1 thus we can say that 1 | j
If something Divides One then it is One or Negative One
Suppose d 1 then d = ± 1
We have that 1 = k d but the only numbers in Z that have a multiplicative inverse are 1 , 1 so d must be one of those or else we have a contradiction.
If Zero Divides a Number, then that Number is Zero
Suppose 0 d then d = 0
By definition we have d = k 0 = 0 so d = 0
0 is Divisible by Everything
for any d Z , d | 0
In the definition of divides take k = 0 , then we can see that 0 = 0 d thus we can say that d | 0
Everything Divides Itself
Let a Z then a a
Clearly 1 a = a therefore a a
Division is Transitive
Suppose a b and b c then a c
We have that b = k a a and c = k b b therefore c = k b ( k a a ) therefore by taking k c = ( k a k b ) we see that a c
If you Divide a Number, then You Divide their Multiples
For any a , b , c Z a b a b c
Suppose that a b therefore there is k Z such that b = k a , therefore multiply both sides to get b c = ( k c ) a and therefore a b c as needed.
If it Divides it's Less than or Equal with Absolute Values
Suppose that n , d Z , such that n 0 then if d divides n , then | d | | n |

We see that n = k d for some k Z , since n 0 then also we must have k , d 0 specifically note that | k | 1 so that we have | n | = | k d | = | k | | d | 1 | d | = | d | so that | n | | d |

We have to specify n 0 because we know that everything divides zero, and therefore without that assumption we could use it to claim that since 42 0 that | 42 | 0 which is clearly false.

Larger Absolute value Implies no Division
for any n , d Z such that n 0 if | d | > | n | then d n
This follows by the contrapositive and this
If two Numbers Divide each other then Their Absolute Values are Equal
For any a , b Z , if a b and b a then | a | = | b |

If a = 0 then because a b then this forces b = 0 so that a = b = 0 , also if we assumed b = 0 the same thing occurs.

In the case that neither of a , b = 0 then recall that if a b we have | a | | b | also since b a then also | a | | b | so that | a | = | b | .

If a Number Divides another Then Given a Common Factor Their Quotients Divide Each Other
Suppose that a , b , d N 1 such that a b and that d is a common divisor of a , b , then a d b d
Divisibility is a Partial Order on the Natural Numbers
Divisibility is a partial order on N 0 .
It is reflexive because we know that everything divides itself, we know it is transitive, and we also know that it is anti-symmetric, because for any n N 0 , | n | = n and using this proposition.

Note that we can't quite get a partial order Z because of the fact that a a .

Linearity of Division
Suppose that a b 1 , , b n then a c 1 b 1 + + c n b n where a , b i , c i Z

For the base case of n = 2 if a b 1 and a b 2 then we know that there are k 1 , k 2 Z such that b 1 = k 1 a and b 2 = k 2 a so that c 1 b 1 + c 2 b 2 = c 1 ( k 1 a ) + c 2 ( k 2 a ) = a ( c 1 k 1 + c 2 k 2 ) .

For the induction step, assume the statement holds true for k N 1 and we'll show that it holds true for k + 1 so suppose that a b 1 , b k + 1 by the induction hypothesis we know that a c 1 b 1 + + c k b k so we get some j Z such that c 1 b 1 + + c k b k = j a and also some j Z such that b k + 1 = j a and therefore c 1 b 1 + + c k b k + c k + 1 b k + 1 = j a + j a = a ( j + j ) so therefore a c 1 b 1 + + c k + 1 b k + 1

Even Number
We say that an integer n Z is even if there is some k Z such that n = 2 k
A power of an Even Number is Even
If n Z is even, then for any m N 1 we have n m is even
If n is even then there is some k Z such that n = 2 k and therefore n m = ( 2 k ) m = 2 m k m = 2 ( 2 m 1 k m ) so that n m is also even.
Odd Number
We say that an integer n Z is odd if there is some k Z such that n = 2 k + 1
A power of an Even Number is Odd
If n Z is odd, then for any m N 0 we have n m is odd

Base case, set m = 0 then n m = 1 which is odd. For the induction step assume it holds true for k N 0 so that n k is odd, which means that there is some j Z such that n k = 2 j + 1 therefore n k + 1 = ( 2 j + 1 ) n but n is odd so there is some j Z such that n = 2 j + 1 and thus n k + 1 = ( 2 j + 1 ) ( 2 j + 1 ) = 4 j j + 2 j + 2 j + 1 = 2 ( 2 j j + j + j ) + 1 hence n k + 1 is prime so the statement follows from the principle of induction.

Product of Two Equal Factors means They are Square Roots
Suppose that a = b c then b = a iff b = c

suppose that b = a then for sake of contradiction if b c then if c < b then we see that a = b c < b b = a a = a which is impossible, on the other hand if c > b = a then we see a = b c < c c < a a which yields the same contradiciton.

Now suppose that b = c therefore a = b c = b b therefore b 2 = a and so b = a as needed, moreover in this case note that c = a as well.

Product Implies Square Root bound on Factors
Suppose that a , b , c N 1 and that b c where a = b c then ( b > a c < a ) ( b < a c > a )
Suppose for the sake of contradiction that it was not true, so that we knew that ( b a c a ) ( b a c a ) Suppose that b a and b a holds true, then b = a since c b then if c < b we see that b c < a a = a which is a contradiction since we know that b c = a , if it turns out that c a and c a it is handeled symetrically.

On the other hand if we know that b a and that c a , since b a then we know that b a , therefore more specifically we see that b < a this implies that a = b c < a a = a which is a contradiction. In the case of c a and b a it follows in a symmetrical manner.

Number To the Power m Minus 1 Divides Number To the Power n if m Divides n
Let a , m , n N 1 then m n ( a m 1 ) ( a n 1 )

We have that n = m k for some k Z and we want to prove that a m k 1 = ( a m 1 ) j for some j Z , a good guess would be that j = a ( m 1 ) k which produces ( a m 1 ) ( a ( m 1 ) k ) = a m k a ( m 1 ) k and so we have to get rid of the a ( m 1 ) k term, which inspires us to try j = a ( m 1 ) k + a ( m 2 ) k which yields ( a m 1 ) ( a ( m 1 ) k + a ( m 2 ) k ) = a k m + a ( m 1 ) k ( a ( m 1 ) k + a ( m 2 ) k ) = a k m a ( m 2 ) k

As we've just run into the same problem as last time we see that adding a ( m 3 ) k would remove the most recent residue term, but then leave the new residue term a ( m 3 ) k . Therefore formally using induction we can show that ( a m 1 ) ( i = 0 m 1 a i k ) = a m k 1 = a n 1 where 1 is really the residue term a ( 0 ) k

a and that m ( a + b ) then m b -->